\section{An Informal Introduction to the \pfc\ language} This section describes \pfc\ . We will start by introducing the language informally through a series of examples drawn from the domain of kinship relations. This will be followed by an example and a description of some of the details of its current implementation. \subsection*{Overview} The \pfc\ package allows one to define forward chaining rules and to add ordinary Prolog assertions into the database in such a way as to trigger any of the \pfc\ rules that are satisfied. An example of a simple \pfc\ rule is: \example gender(P,male) => male(P) \end{verbatim}\end{quote} This rule states that whenever the fact unifying with $gender(P,male)$ is added to the database, then the fact $male(P)$ is true. If this fact is not already in the database, it will be added. In any case, a record will be made that the validity of the fact $male(P)$ depends, in part, on the validity of this forward chaining rule and the fact which triggered it. To make the example concrete, if we add $gender(john,male)$, then the fact $male(john)$ will be added to the database unless it was already there. In order to make this work, it is necessary to use the predicate {\em add/1} rather than {\em assert/1} in order to assert \pfc\ rules and any facts which might appear in the lhs of a \pfc\ rule. \subsection*{Compound Rules} A slightly more complex rule is one in which the rule's left hand side is a conjunction or disjunction of conditions: \example parent(X,Y),female(X) => mother(X,Y) mother(X,Y);father(X,Y) => parent(X,Y) \end{verbatim}\end{quote} The first rule has the effect of adding the assertion $mother(X,Y)$ to the database whenever $parent(X,Y)$ and $female(X)$ are simultaneously true for some $X$ and $Y$. Again, a record will be kept that indicates that any fact $mother(X,Y)$ added by the application of this rule is justified by the rule and the two triggering facts. If any one of these three clauses is removed from the database, then all facts solely dependent on them will also be removed. Similarly, the second example rule derives the parent relationship whenever either the mother relationship or the father relationship is known. In fact, the lhs of a \pfc\ rule can be an arbitrary conjunction or disjunction of facts. For example, we might have a rule like: \example P, (Q;R), S => T \end{verbatim}\end{quote} \pfc\ handles such a rule by putting it into conjunctive normal form. Thus the rule above is the equivalent to the two rules: \example P,Q,S => T P,R,S => T \end{verbatim}\end{quote} \subsection*{Bi-conditionals} \pfc\ has a limited ability to express bi-conditional rules, such as: \example mother(P1,P2) <=> parent(P1,P2), female(P1). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} In particular, adding a rule of the form {\tt P<=>Q} is the equivalent to adding the two rules {\tt P=>Q} and {\tt Q=>P}. The limitations on the use of bi-conditional rules stem from the restrictions that the two derived rules be valid horn clauses. This is discussed in a later section. \subsection*{Backward-Chaining \pfc\ Rules} \pfc\ includes a special kind of backward chaining rule which is used to generate all possible solutions to a goal that is sought in the process of forward chaining. Suppose we wished to define the {\em ancestor} relationship as a \pfc\ rule. This could be done as: \example parent(P1,P2) => ancestor(P1,P2). parent(P1,P2), ancestor(P2,P3) => ancestor(P1,P3). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} However, adding these rules will generate a large number of assertions, most of which will never be needed. An alternative is to define the {\em ancestor} relationship by way of backward chaining rules which are invoked whenever a particular ancestor relationship is needed. In \pfc\, this need arises whenever facts matching the relationship are sought while trying a forward chaining rule. \example ancestor(P1,P2) <= {\+var(P1)}, parent(P1,X), ancestor(X,P2). ancestor(P1,P2) <= {var(P1),\+var(P2)}, parent(X,P2), ancestor(P2,X). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} \subsection*{Conditioned Rules} It is sometimes necessary to add some further condition on a rule. Consider a definition of sibling which states: \begin{quote} Two people are siblings if they have the same mother and the same father. No one can be his own sibling. \end{quote} This definition could be realized by the following \pfc\ rule \example mother(Ma,P1), mother(Ma,P2), {P1\==P2}, father(Pa,P1), father(Pa,P2) => sibling(P1,P2). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} Here we must add a condition to the lhs of the rule which states the the variables $P1$ and $P2$ must not unify. This is effected by enclosing an arbitrary Prolog goal in braces. When the goals to the left of such a bracketed condition have been fulfilled, then it will be executed. If it can be satisfied, then the rule will remain active, otherwise it will be terminated. \subsection*{Negation} We sometimes want to draw an inference from the absence of some knowledge. For example, we might wish to encode the default rule that a person is assumed to be male unless we have evidence to the contrary: \example person(P), ~female(P) => male(P). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} A lhs term preceded by a $\sim$ is satisfied only if {\em no} fact in the database unifies with it. Again, the \pfc\ system records a justification for the conclusion which, in this case, states that it depends on the absence of the contradictory evidence. The behavior of this rule is demonstrated in the following dialogue: \example ?- add(person(P), ~female(P) => male(P)). yes ?- add(person(alex)). yes ?- male(alex). yes ?- add(female(alex)). yes ?- male(alex) no \end{verbatim}\end{quote} As a slightly more complicated example, consider a rule which states that we should assume that the parents of a person are married unless we know otherwise. Knowing otherwise might consist of either knowing that one of them is married to a yet another person or knowing that they are divorced. We might try to encode this as follows: \example parent(P1,X), parent(P2,X), {P1\==P2}, ~divorced(P1,P2), ~spouse(P1,P3), {P3\==P2}, ~spouse(P2,P4), {P4\==P1} => spouse(P1,P2). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} Unfortunately, this won't work. The problem is that the conjoined condition \example ~spouse(P1,P3),{P3\==P2} \end{verbatim}\end{quote} does not mean what we want it to mean - that there is no $P3$ distinct from $P2$ that is the spouse of $P1$. Instead, it means that $P1$ is not married to any $P3$. We need a way to move the qualification \verb+{P3\==P2}+ inside the scope of the negation. To achieve this, we introduce the notion of a qualified goal. A lhs term $P/C$, where P is a positive atomic condition, is true only if there is a database fact unifying with $P$ and condition $C$ is satisfiable. Similarly, a lhs term $\sim P/C$, where P is a positive atomic condition, is true only if there is no database fact unifying with $P$ for which condition $C$ is satisfiable. Our rule can now be expressed as follows: \example parent(P1,X), parent(P2,X)/(P1\==P2), ~divorced(P1,P2), ~spouse(P1,P3)/(P3\==P2), ~spouse(P2,P4)/(P4\==P1) => spouse(P1,P2). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} \subsection*{Procedural Interpretation} Note that the procedural interpretation of a \pfc\ rule is that the conditions in the lhs are checked {\em from left to right}. One advantage to this is that the programmer can chose an order to the conditions in a rule to minimize the number of partial instantiations. % include an example here Another advantage is that it allows us to write rules like the following: \example at(Obj,Loc1),at(Obj,Loc2)/{Loc1\==Loc2} => {remove(at(Obj,Loc1))}. \end{verbatim}\end{quote} Although the declarative reading of this rule can be questioned, its procedural interpretation is clear and useful: \begin{quotation} If an object is known to be at location $Loc1$ and an assertion is added that it is at some location $Loc2$, distinct from $Loc1$, then the assertion that it is at $Loc1$ should be removed. \end{quotation} \subsection*{The Right Hand Side} The examples seen so far have shown a rules rhs as a single proposition to be ``added'' to the database. The rhs of a \pfc\ rule has some richness as well. The rhs of a rule is a conjunction of facts to be ``added'' to the database and terms enclosed in brackets which represent conditions/actions which are executed. As a simple example, consider the conclusions we might draw upon learning that one person is the mother of another: \example mother(X,Y) => female(X), parent(X,Y), adult(X). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} As another example, consider a rule which detects bigamists and sends an appropriate warning to the proper authorities: \example spouse(X,Y), spouse(X,Z), {Y\==Z} => bigamist(X), {format("~N~w is a bigamist, married to both ~w and ~w~n",[X,Y,Z])}. \end{verbatim}\end{quote} Each element in the rhs of a rule is processed from left to right --- assertions being added to the database with appropriate support and conditions being satisfied. If a condition can not be satisfied, the rest of the rhs is not processed. We would like to allow rules to be expressed as bi-conditional in so far a possible. Thus, an element in the lhs of a rule should have an appropriate meaning on the rhs as well. What meaning should be assigned to the conditional fact construction (e.g. $P/Q$) which can occur in a rules lhs? Such a term in the rhs of a rule is interpreted as a {\em conditioned assertion}. Thus the assertion $P/Q$ will match a condition $P\prime$ in the lhs of a rule only if $P$ and $P\prime$ unify and the condition $Q$ is satisfiable. For example, consider the rules that says that an object being located at one place is reason to believe that it is not at any other place: \example at(X,L1) => not(at(X,L2))/L2\==L1 \end{verbatim}\end{quote} Note that a {\em conditioned assertion} is essentially a Horn clause. We would express this fact in Prolog as the backward chaining rule: \example not(at(X,L2)) :- at(X,L1),L1\==L2. \end{verbatim}\end{quote} The difference is, of course, that the addition of such a conditioned assertion will trigger forward chaining whereas the assertion of a new backward chaining rule will not. \subsection*{The Truth Maintenance System} As discussed in the previous section, a forward reasoning system has special needs for some kind of {\em truth maintenance system}. The \pfc\ system has a rather straightforward TMS system which records justifications for each fact deduced by a \pfc\ rule. Whenever a fact is removed from the database, any justifications in which it plays a part are also removed. The facts that are justified by a removed justification are checked to see if they are still supported by some other justifications. If they are not, then those facts are also removed. Such a TMS system can be relatively expensive to use and is not needed for many applications. Consequently, its use and nature are optional in \pfc\ and are controlled by the predicate $pfcTmsMode/1$. The possible cases are three: \begin{itemize} \item $pfcTmsMode(full)$ - The fact is removed unless it has {\em well found\-ed support} (WFS). A fact has WFS if it is supported by the $user$ or by $God$ or by a justification all of whose justificees have WFS\footnote{Determining if a fact has WFS requires detecting local cycles - see \cite{mcdermott85} for an introduction}. \item $pfcTmsMode(local)$ - The fact is removed if it has no supporting justifications. \item $pfcTmsMode(none)$ - The fact is never removed. \end{itemize} A fact is considered to be supported by $God$ if it is found in the database with no visible means of support. That is, if \pfc\ discovers an assertion in the database that can take part in a forward reasoning step, and that assertion is not supported by either the user or a forward deduction, then a note is added that the assertion is supported by $God$. This adds additional flexibility in interfacing systems employing \pfc\ to other Prolog applications. For some applications, it is useful to be able to justify actions performed in the rhs of a rule. To allow this, \pfc\ supports the idea of declaring certain actions to be {\em undoable} and provides the user with a way of specifying methods to undo those actions. Whenever an action is executed in the rhs of a rule and that action is undoable, then a record is made of the justification for that action. If that justification is later invalidated (e.g. through the retraction of one of its justificees) then the support is checked for the action in the same way as it would be for an assertion. If the action does not have support, then \pfc\ trys each of the methods it knows to undo the action until one of them succeeds. In fact, in \pfc\ , one declares an action as undoable just by defining a method to accomplish the undoing. This is done via the predicate $pfcUndo/2$. The predicate $pfcUndo(A1,A2)$ is true if executing $A2$ is a possible way to undo the execution of $A1$. For example, we might want to couple an assertional representation of a set of graph nodes with a graphical display of them through the use of \pfc\ rules: \example at(N,XY) => {displayNode(N,XY)}. arc(N1,N2) => {displayArc(N1,N2}. pfcUndo(displayNode(N,XY),eraseNode(N,XY)). pfcUndo(displayArc(N1,N2),eraseArc(N1,N2)). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} \subsection*{Limitations} The \pfc\ system has several limitations, most of which it inherits from its Prolog roots. One of the more obvious of these is that \pfc\ rules must be expressible as a set of horn clauses. The practical effect is that the rhs of a rule must be a conjunction of terms which are either assertions to be added to the database or actions to be executed. Negated assertions and disjunctions are not permitted, making rules like \example parent(X,Y) <=> mother(X,Y);father(X,Y) male(X) <=> ~female(X) \end{verbatim}\end{quote} ill-formed. Another restrictions is that all variables in a \pfc\ rule have implicit universal quantification. As a result, any variables in the rhs of a rule which remain uninstantiated when the lhs has been fully satisfied retain their universal quantification. This prevents us from using a rule like \example father(X,Y), parent(Y,Z) <=> grandfather(X,Z). \end{verbatim}\end{quote} with the desired results. If we do add this rule and assert {\em grandfather(john,mary)}, then \pfc\ will add the two independent assertions {\em father(john,\_)} (i.e. ``John is the father of everyone'') and {\em parent(\_,mary)} (i.e. ``Everyone is Mary's parent''). Another problem associated with the use of the Prolog database is that assertions containing variables actually contain ``copies'' of the variables. Thus, when the conjunction \example add(father(adam,X)), X=able \end{verbatim}\end{quote} is evaluated, the assertion \verb#father(adam,_G032)# is added to the da\-ta\-base, where \_G032 is a new variable which is distinct from X. As a consequence, it is never unified with {\em able}.